|
|
|
|
Chapter 10 Precedent at Dar al-Hikma
|
Back in Chapter 2 we began the vignette of
al-Kirmani and al-Akhram, only to set it aside for consideration at a later
time. Now I'd like to recall these two gentlemen and continue their interrupted
history. Both men contribute to Dar al-Hikma's precedent its
harbinger of Metaphysics by Default.
Looking first at al-Kirmani's contribution:
Al-Kirmani was an
orthodox Ismaili theologian. His letter of warning to al-Akhram was
typical of his attempts to herd radicals back into the fold of convenient orthodoxy.
As he scolded al-Akhram he bore down also upon the popular works of Abu
Ya'qub al-Sijistani, a tenth-century Neoplatonic
Ismaili philosopher. Al-Kirmani's concern with al-Sijistani centered on the man's
notion that the soul is "forgetful," in the Neoplatonic sense. [1] Paul Walker illumines
al-Sijistani's position:
The physical world is attractive and the
lower preoccupations of the soul hold its attention. Baser soul
becomes enmeshed, enthralled, infatuated with the ephemeral effects in
momentary pleasures and experiences. The timeless stability of
intellect seems less exciting by comparison. As a result soul has a
tendency to sink lower and lower, to plunge into material being and the
physical world to its ultimate depths. It then becomes forgetful
of its spiritual origin.
[Walker
comments:] Forgetting in soul implies that there was something to forget,
something like a previous existence.... [2]
Al-Kirmani was sensitive to a possible
heresy in al-Sijistani's position. Walker adds detail to that position,
and recounts al-Kirmani's investigation:
Although al-Sijistani explicitly
challenges and rejects transmigration in the extant material written by him,
it is hard to confirm his exact view of this particular form of
metempsychosis since the very concept of soul "forgetting" and
"remembering" presupposes that is [sic] has an existence outside
of the individual body to which it is temporarily attached. Without
question al-Sijistani recognizes in some manner the concept of soul
"forgetting" her own world. Does the soul therefore
"remember" a previous existence? Does it "forget"
its bodily life once it separates from the sensations of physical
being? These are additional questions which might indicate the
relationship between the soul in body and the soul once freed of body.
The
thirty-seventh iqlid of al-Maqalid asks the latter question in its title: "That
Soul when it Separates from the Body Does Any of its Knowledge Cease or
Not?" Al-Sijistani's answer is that temporal events and knowledge
of them certainly do come to an end because soul once outside of body is not
confined either by physical fact or temporal sequence. The discrete facts
of a corporeal life no longer possess significance; they cease to
exist. The implication is clear: soul no longer remembers its
individual, particular existence since it now participates in true, timeless
knowledge which is mind itself.
Al-Kirmani
noted this problem in his Riyad and recorded his
own unease with the ideas of al-Sijistani about soul's
"forgetting." The implications he sees in this doctrine lead
eventually to the objectionable doctrine of transmigration, but al-Kirmani
goes on to exonerate al-Sijistani.... [3]
What is most noteworthy in all this is the
fact that al-Kirmani associated transmigration with al-Sijistani's philosophy of
the soul's "forgetfulness." He drew a connection between
forgetfulness and transmigration; even though al-Sijistani did not, himself,
teach transmigration.
This connection
has its parallel in Metaphysics by Default. Back in Chapter 9 we saw how
"mortal amnesia" leads to the concept of existential passage. It is a
prerequisite of the inference. Should memory loss at the end of life be less than
complete, existential passage would be effectively blocked. But a complete mortal
amnesia sets up conditions for passage.
So al-Kirmani was
right to isolate al-Sijistani's doctrine for careful scrutiny. Then as
now, forgetfulness opens the door to transmigration.
But we should not
infer that al-Kirmani was himself interested in exploring this fine point of
transmigration philosophy. Just the opposite: his pronouncements on
the subject were intended to be negative, prohibitory. He could bind
forgetfulness to transmigration with a thread of "guilt by
association," and that sufficed for the purpose of his orthodox mission.
Al-Akhram is another story. He and
his supporters were keen to graft transmigration onto Muslim theology.
Neoplatonic philosophy aided their cause. [4] Al-Kirmani was aware of
this. He may have refused to answer al-Akhram's question on the
soul's nature for fear that a detailed response might give his
opponent some advantage in the debate. To be sure, al-Kirmani would have had
little to gain by acquainting al-Akhram with other philosophies supportive of
transmigration, such as al-Sijistani's forgetfulness theory.
That sort of intellectual matchmaking was not in al-Kirmani's
charter.
Al-Akhram died
a year after his debate with al-Kirmani. [5] Other
leaders took al-Akhram's place in the radical movement, and they went on to canonize
the movement's ideas as a formal religious philosophy. That canon has
been preserved. It is now a sacred text of the Muehhideen [6] Druze community. The canon is
comprised of one hundred and eleven epistles, a few of which discuss
transmigration. [7] Most
of the canonical transmigration ideas are Neoplatonic — but the text
harbors surprises. I reprint extended quotations from Epistle 70 below, with
a few notes at the end. The quotations begin with a statement we've seen
before, back in Chapter 2:
It is claimed that the soul was dropped
into this world from without, without being apprised of any guilt attached
to it.... I say that if this was done as an opportunity for the soul
to be refined and purified then this world (earth) in God's justice should
have been superior to the place of its regress and defilement.
If it was dropped as retribution for
some committed wrong, then this environment fits its guilt and further
repentence [sic] and devotion become useless and superfluous for it has
already been charged and condemned and is paying in hurt and penance and
nothing can change its plight. This environment is set aside,
therefore, as an abode of the unclean and cannot be a temple for worship nor
a medium for rehabilitation.
If the
preceding hypothesis holds and the soul was dropped on earth because of
slip, error and sin then the soul will be here for good. No one on
earth can live free from error and sin and if error and sin brought the soul
to earth the soul's multiplicity of errors and sins in this earthly life
will be added reason to continue its residence hereon. The soul will
not, therefore, leave this world.
If they admit
that the soul thrived in this world and was cleansed and became educated
after it was ignorant, then this world where it flourished must be superior
to that in which she stumbled, was tainted and fell.
I say what
Reason spells out namely: that no honest and perceptive person can but admit
that the soul has advanced from ignorance to knowledge in this world despite
its errors and trespasses and has no reason whatsoever to abandon it and
must perforce elect to stay in it and will return to it every time.... [8]
The savants of old agreed that the soul
reaches its highest stage of development in the midst of nature's
environment. Justice and reason would indicate that the soul, joined
to the body in this world's atmosphere, is ideal for the soul and more
creditable and nobler than if it were done after it leaves the body, for,
joined to the body and ruling it, it dominates the world also and reigns by
virtue of its own power and authority over this order of nature.
Whoever disagrees, let him come forward and show us what the soul has done
independently and on its own after it has discarded its body [sic] garb. [9]
The soul does not act away from and
apart of the human body. If it did so, it could not talk and
communicate and such act would come to naught. Shaizary's opinion that
the soul withdraws unto itself at dream-time and returns to tell what it had
seen gives us no new insight. It only reflects vaguely what we see in
nature and in our natural lives through the senses and adds no new
experience or knowledge. The congenitally blind cannot conceive of
natural images in his dreams for he never had sight to be cognizant of the
form of those images. [10]
Given the time and place of authorship, those were fighting words.
The Druze developed these bold metaphysical ideas with respect for Greek and Hellenistic precedents. We can see something of their
Greek inspiration by comparing their opinion on dreams with that of a revered Greek authority. Their opinion, stated above, is reminiscent of
Aristotle's own:
[A]s in a liquid, if one vehemently
disturbs it, sometimes no reflected image appears, while at other times one
appears, indeed, but utterly distorted, so as to seem quite unlike its
original; while, when once the motion has ceased, the reflected images are
clear and plain; in the same manner during sleep the phantasms, or residuary
movements, which are based upon the sensory impressions, become sometimes
quite obliterated by the above described motion when too violent; while at
other times the sights are indeed seen, but confused and weird....[11]
It would be overreaching to claim
Aristotelian authority for the Druze passage concerning dreams, but the
similarity reminds us of the influence which Aristotle exerted at Dar
al-Hikma. We've seen in Chapter 2 that the chief Ismaili theologian,
al-Kirmani, did himself prefer an Aristotelian version of soul to the
Neoplatonic. And I'd like to introduce one more palace Aristotelian, [12] a contemporary of
al-Kirmani [13] and
al-Akhram. This Aristotelian was the scientist Abu Ali Mohammed ibn al-Hasan ibn
al-Haitham, pre-eminent physicist and mathematician of the Fatimid empire. [14]
Ibn al-Haitham's Optics textbook provides an informed theory of
perception, quite advanced for its time in attention to experimental
detail. Here is T. J. De Boer's paraphrased translation of the
theory. Note the importance which ibn al-Haitham places upon the timing of perception, especially as it concerns the
temporal operation of the nervous system.
In the "Optics" the
psychological remarks on Seeing and on Sense-Perception in general
are of special interest for us. Here he exerts himself to separate the
individual Moments of the Perception, and to give prominence to the
condition of Time as characterizing the whole process.
Perception
then is a compound process, arising out of (1) sensation, (2) comparison of
several sensations or of the present sensation with the memory-image which
has been gradually formed in the soul as a result of earlier sensations, and
(3) recognition, in such fashion that we recognize the present percept as
equivalent to the memory-image. Comparison and recognition are not
activities of the Senses, which merely receive impressions passively, but
they devolve upon the Understanding as the faculty of judgment.
Ordinarily the whole process goes forward unconsciously or semi-consciously,
and it is only through reflection that it is brought within our
consciousness, and that the apparently simplex is separated into its
component parts.
The process
of Perception is gone through very quickly. The more practice a man
has in this respect, and the oftener a perception is repeated, the more
firmly is the memory-image stamped upon the soul, and the more rapidly is
recognition or perception effected. The cause of this is that the new
sensation is supplemented by the image which is already present in the
soul. One might thus be disposed to think that Perception was an
instantaneous act, at least after long practice. That, however, would
be erroneous, for not only is every sensation attended by a corresponding
change localized in the sense-organ, which demands a certain time, but also,
between the stimulation of the organ and the consciousness of the perception
an interval of time must elapse, corresponding to the transmission of the
stimulus for some distance along the nerves. That it needs time, for
example, to perceive a colour, is proved by the rotating circle of colours,
which shows us merely a mixed colour, because on account of the rapid
movement we have no time to perceive the individual colours. [15]
While developing Metaphysics by Default, I
have sometimes wondered whether the Fatimid philosophers at Dar al-Hikma might
have guessed at existential passage before, back during the eleventh-century reign of al-Hakim. It remains a
possibility. To see just how close they came we may consider, as a
unit, four ideas which were popular at the palace and subject to vitriolic debate by
1017. These four ideas were:
- Ibn al-Haitham's theory of perception, in which all
perceived sensation was understood to depend upon temporal nervous activity.
- Al-Sijistani's theory of the soul's
"forgetfulness."
- The Druze' Aristotelian opinion that "the soul
does not act away from and apart of the human body."
- The Neoplatonic tradition of transmigration
philosophy.
We can imagine a hypothetical scenario, as a
historical fancy:
What if al-Hakim's reign had prospered through the eleventh century, [16]
and palace scholarship continued undisturbed for a few generations? Had
this happened, proponents of these four ideas might have synthesized from them a
medieval version of existential passage.
The historical
circumstances place restrictions on what such a philosophy could be. To
begin with, the axioms of a "medieval existential passage" would need
to adhere to the four incipient ideas. Also, since we're conjecturing an
eleventh-century synthesis, any European Renaissance
science is out-of-bounds. Finally, we must deny our fancied medieval
philosophers access to any definition of personal identity, as John
Locke opened that field in 1694.
Within these
reasonable limits, the following synthesis may
have been possible:
{an imagined synthesis not a quotation}
At death,
temporal nervous activity ceases. This quiescence liberates the soul;
calming its excitations and releasing it from worldly preoccupations by
means of a "forgetfulness of perception." Divinely
afflicted, the soul is entranced within the timeless stability of intellect
and is unable to perceive sensation or the flow of time. This
condition persists until Universal Soul transmigrates the individual soul to
another human body. Thereafter the new body's nervous system transmits
perception of time and sensation to the soul again, lowering it from
forgetfulness and into new life.
Such a development of Ismaili thought, had
it occurred, would have drawn the radicals' transmigration mechanism closer to
the existential passage of Metaphysics by Default. It would have made a
good "transitional" philosophy: a link in the conceptual chain which
leads from the four incipient ideas to Metaphysics by Default proper.
But I should
repeat for the sake of absolute clarity: this did not happen. No such transitional text has ever
been found, nor have we reason to expect any such text will be found. I've only
presented the imagined synthesis as an exercise of the historical imagination. It's one
path Ismaili philosophers could have followed, in theory, but did not follow in actual fact.
The ashen Hills of Books blocked their way.
That being said, I'll quote one more Middle
Eastern author before moving on.
In the sixteenth century the Druze sheikh Abdul Ghaffar wrote a book
of philosophy entitled Points and
Circles (Al-Nuqat wal-Dawayer). [17] It is
respected even today by Druze authorities. [18]
In this book
Sheikh Abdul Ghaffar presents a blunt argument against "past life recall," or
mere "talk," as Druze elders denoted it. He emphasizes the
body's supposed psychological functions, and he posits a transmigration event
which occurs instantaneously over any distance. It's a philosophy which confounds expectation — by threading together all four of the
metaphysical ideas which were incipient at Dar al-Hikma.
Here is the relevant passage from Abdul Ghaffar's Points and
Circles:
The talking Spirit cannot remember save
through the physical memory. It cannot think save through the brain in
the body. It cannot differentiate except through the distinguishing
power resident in the body. It cannot memorize except through the
memorizing organ in the body. Distances don't matter to it when it
leaves (at death) one body for another, with no lapse in time in the
process....
The Spirit
while resident in the body, participates in all its activities. When
it departs, it loses all factual material it had acquired in it.
The spiritual
advances the higher Spirit has gained, however, are retained....
And it
remains true and worth repeating that 'In this earthly life, souls do not
know their past.' [19]
Here, in this one passage, Abdul Ghaffar appears to have synthesized, or
at least syncretized,
transmigration concepts which bear a striking resemblance to mortal amnesia and
existential passage. For Abdul Ghaffar, forgetfulness is complete at the end of life, and transmigration occurs instantaneously, irrespective of distance. The only notable discrepancy in Abdul Ghaffar's formulation is his appended assertion concerning "spiritual
advances": a discrepancy not entirely without remedy. [20] Elsewhere Abdul Ghaffar's parsimonious deductions elicit
our wonder, being as
they are so suggestive of Metaphysics by Default — and so retrograde to the expansive
religious traditions of his age.
Regrettably, Abdul Ghaffar quickly abandons his
intriguing hint at the modern thesis, veering back into
Neoplatonism in accordance with the established Druze canon. [21] To put his
aversion in perspective: under Ismaili Neoplatonic schemes, Universal Soul
orchestrates passage to the afterlife according to rules of
justice and emanationism. [22] These rules are unrelated to any physical account of
the soul's operation. They hearken back to Plotinus' hypostases, [23] which have no physical
properties to speak of.
The Druze are an independent branch of the Ismaili zeitgeist. This sect has
maintained its Neoplatonic transmigration tradition into the present day. To
Neoplatonists like the Druze, the passage executive — Universal Soul — remains an
incorporeal psychological entity (Sheikh Abdul Ghaffar's suggestive text
notwithstanding). It seems never to have occurred to the Druze, or to anyone, that Universal Soul
might best be understood not as an incorporeal, but as a corporeal and therefore ubiquitous psychology; i.e., subjectivity.
For this reason existential passage, being premised
on corporeal psychological entities exclusively, is incompatible with
Neoplatonic transmigration
tradition — just because Neoplatonism, as conventionally formulated, is ever premised on incorporeal soul.
So, historically, it stands to reason that this incompatibility would have
prevented Muslim Neoplatonists from embracing even the "medieval" existential
passage I floated in the historical fancy. That speculation, like Abdul Ghaffar's real venture, draws more
attention to corporeal limits than Neoplatonists would like.
It would be heartening to learn of philosophers from the past who've ventured
closer to Metaphysics by Default. It seems however that none have done so. My own review [24] of the history of philosophy has turned up no
better precedent than the abortive effort at Dar al-Hikma. I'm glad at least to
have been able to present that unique and surprising history. I hope it has been of some
interest to the reader.
For further
reading I include a few references on related subjects:
- Islamic
Hellenism and Fatimid scholarship[25]
- the caliphate of al-Hakim[26]
- Fatimid
Cairo[27]
- the
origin of the Druze[28]
Also I've assembled some images of Dar al-Hikma and Old Cairo on a supplementary page, here.
Significant Addendum — August 2004
No better precedent has yet fluttered down from the history stacks, but a
contemporary philosopher has recently surprised me with a paper entitled,
Death, Nothingness, and Subjectivity. In this paper
philosopher and naturalist Thomas W. Clark argues for a novel metaphysical
concept: "generic subjective continuity". As it happens, this concept
proves to be functionally identical to existential passage. More
surprisingly, we find upon close examination that Mr. Clark's argument for
generic subjective continuity parallels my initial argument for existential
passage (Chapter 9) at all the critical points. Readers who've grasped my argument
will find little difficulty in translating between Chapter 9 and Mr. Clark's admirable paper.
For me, this has been a development more heartening than the
discovery of historical precedent. Precedent is agreement among the dead. This is agreement among the living.
Mr. Clark has generously offered a summary comparison of existential passage and generic subjective continuity. I reproduce his statement below:
In a wonderfully written monograph (a book, really), "Metaphysics By Default,"
Wayne Stewart presents an independently developed thesis directly parallel to
my argument in "Death, Nothingness, and Subjectivity" (DNS). Without
having encountered my paper, Mr. Stewart uses very much the same thought experiment
to support the intuition of generic subjective continuity, what he calls
"existential passage" (see in particular Chapter 9). The passage across
birth and death, as he describes it, is "a shift of perceived existential
'moment,' a natural relocation of the awareness of existence." This seems
very close to the idea in DNS that what we should anticipate at death is the
continuing "sense of always having been present."
I'm happy to report that
Stewart's thesis, like mine, is entirely physicalistic, in that the basis for
consciousness and subjectivity is taken to be the brain (more generally, a
suitably enhanced central nervous system), so that nothing is literally
carried over between subjects. Yet subjectivity continues across objective gaps between physically instantiated subjects, and this is a psychologically important fact for us.
Needless to say, it was very
gratifying to learn of Mr. Stewart's work, which I highly recommend to
your attention.
— Thomas W. Clark, August 23, 2004
This completes our recovery of the
historical precedent for Metaphysics by Default — precedent now augmented by Mr. Clark's coincident paper.
(And that's not all. Recently correspondents have brought to my attention some existential-passage reasoning in the papers of three other writers: William Spaulding, David Darling and Mark Sharlow. See endnote [29] for details.)
In our mind's eye this philosophical amity can fit in place as the second of five stepping stones strewn across the river
Lethe. In subsequent chapters we will uncover properties of the
metaphysics which distinguish it from historical transmigration philosophies. We can imagine these distinguishing properties as the three stepping
stones yet separating us from the living world that waits beyond the river.
next Chapter 11: Passage Types
see also Chapter 10
Supplement: Images of Dar al-Hikma
|
Chapter 10 Endnotes
|
[1] Al-Sijistani's philosophy of forgetfulness appears to elaborate on
Plato's own vision, a vision which was integral to Plato's transmigration
philosophy. Quoting from Plato, "Phaedrus," The Works of Plato, trans. B. Jowett (New York: The Dial Press, n.d.)
406, 408. Available online:
"[W]hen [the soul]... fails to behold
the vision of truth, and through some ill-hap sinks beneath the double load
of forgetfulness and vice, and her feathers fall from her and she drops to
earth, then the law ordains that this soul shall in the first generation
pass, not into that of any other animal, but only of man.... ...[A]ll men do not
easily recall the things of the other world; they may have seen them for a
short time only, or they may have been unfortunate when they fell to earth,
and may have lost the memory of the holy things which they saw there through
some evil and corrupting association. Few there are who retain the
remembrance of them sufficiently...."
[2] Paul E. Walker, Abu Ya'qub al-Sijistani:
Intellectual Missionary (London: I.B. Tauris, 1996) 43.
[3] Paul E. Walker, Early Philosophical Shiism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1993) 99.
[4] For historical notes on the transmigration beliefs of some early
eleventh-century Ismaili extremists, see Abu-Izzeddin
116-17. See also Bryer 52.2 (1975): 245, 247; and 53.1 (1976): 10. For
translations of several eleventh-century Druze
epistles concerning reincarnation, see al-Najjar 87-107.
[5] Al-Akhram was put to death after accidentally sparking a
riot. The riot arose when al-Akhram tried to divinize the caliph in
public. This event is only distantly related to the philosophical issues
discussed in the essay. See Bryer 52:1 (1975): 63-83.
[6] The noun is "Muehhidun," which translates as
"Unitarians," or "believers in absolute monotheism."
[7] Primarily Epistles 15, 57, and 66-71. A few passages from this text
are translated to English in al-Najjar 106-07.
[8] from Epistle 70 of the Druze canon, by Baha' al-Din; al-Najjar
97.
[9] from Epistle 70 of the Druze canon, by Baha' al-Din; al-Najjar
99.
[10] from Epistle 70 of the Druze canon, by Baha' al-Din; al-Najjar
105-06.
[11] Aristotle, "On Dreams," Basic
Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941)
622-23, Chapter 3, 461a 14-22.
[12] T. J. De Boer, The History of Philosophy in
Islam, trans. Edward R. Jones (New Delhi: Cosmo Publications, 1983) 150.
Quoting:
"In [ibn al-Haitham's] view philosophy
should be the basis of all the sciences. He found it in the writings
of Aristotle, inasmuch as that sage had best understood how to knit
sense-perception into a coherent whole with rational knowledge. With
eagerness therefore he studied and illustrated Aristotle's works, for the
use and profit of mankind, as well as to exercise his own intellect and
provide a treasure and consolation for his old age. Of these labours,
however, nothing seems to have been preserved for us."
[13] No particular correspondence between al-Kirmani and ibn al-Haitham
has survived or is known to have existed. But as these men were the most
famous academics at the palace, they most likely encountered each other
frequently at Dar al-Hikma, and at meetings with Caliph al-Hakim.
[16] Caliph al-Hakim disappeared in A.D. 1021 ( 412 A.H.) at the age of
36, under mysterious circumstances. See Assaad 182-92 for possible
explanations of the disappearance.
[17] Sheikh Zeiniddin Abdul Ghaffar, Al-Nuqat
wal-Dawayer (Points and Circles), (Lebanon: Al-Maktabah, 1999). Reprint of
original, 1557. Reprint available [in Arabic] through al-Maktabah
(alMaktabah.com), P.O. Box 1998, Beirut 11, Lebanon.
[18] Verified by this author on-site among the Druze communities of
Lebanon; February, 1999.
[19] Al-Najjar 106-07. Arabic quotation from Abdul Ghaffar
117-20.
[20] Metaphysics by Default does not posit a personal mechanism for retention of such
advances, or any other qualities, between lives. (For a consideration of the broader difficulties of karma doctrines, see Chapter 11, note 1.)
The concept of "spiritual advancement" is not, however, exclusively personal. It has an impersonal aspect as
well. To illustrate: When an author pens some insight on the human condition, that act commits the author's personal spiritual advancement
to an impersonal medium. And when a reader grasps the author's meaning, the impersonal record then enters into the
reader's personal thoughts. Thus the spiritual advancement is transmitted: impersonally, but nonetheless
effectively. (Of course, any noble text can prove this assertion. One volume which I feel deserves special mention is
Adler and Van Doren's Great Treasury of Western Thought. It's an inspired compendium.
The selections truly constitute a treasury of spiritual advances transmitted to us from our predecessors. I recommend the work highly.)
[21] Points and Circles has 38
chapters. Chapters 3, 4, 5, 10, 28, 34 and 37 are arguably
Neoplatonic. Other chapters address morality, the relation of body to
soul, the duality of good and evil, and divine justice.
[22] See Paul E. Walker, "The Universal Soul and the Particular
Soul in Ismaili Neoplatonism," Neoplatonism and
Islamic Thought, ed. Parviz Morewedge (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1992) 149-66.
[23] The hypostases are defined in the Enneads of Plotinus. See Plotinus, "Enneads," The Essential Plotinus, trans. Elmer O'Brien, 2 nd edition (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1986) 90-105, (V, 1
[10]). Available online.
[24] Detailed analyses of a wide range of potential precedents can be
found in Lawrence E. Sullivan, ed., Death, Afterlife, and
the Soul (New York: MacMillan Publishing Company, 1989); E. S. P. Haynes, The Belief in Personal Immortality, 2 nd edition, revised (London: Grand Richards, 1925); Ernest G.
Braham, The Problem of the Self and Immortality: An
Estimate and Criticism of the Subject from Descartes to Kant; Ernest G.
Braham, Personality and Immortality in Post-Kantian
Thought; Steven J. Kaplan, ed., Concepts of
Transmigration: Perspectives on Reincarnation (Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen
Press, 1995); Joseph Head and S. L. Cranston, eds., Reincarnation in World Thought (New York: Causeway Books, published by
arrangement with the Julian Press, ca. 1967).
[25] Franz Rosenthal, The Classical Heritage in
Islam (London: Routledge, 1994); Parviz Morewedge, ed. Neoplatonism and Islamic Thought (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1992); F. E. Peters, Aristotle and the Arabs: The
Aristotelian Tradition in Islam (New York: New York University Press, 1968);
De Boer, The History of Philosophy in Islam; Heinz
Halm, The Fatimids and their Traditions of
Learning.
[26] Assaad, The Reign of Al-Hakim Bi Amr
Allah. It is unfortunate that many medieval histories embellish stories of the
Fatimid era with secondhand references and politically-motivated slanders.
Dr. Assaad's meticulous reconstruction of al-Hakim's era is an exemplary treatment of
difficult source materials.
[27] Yaacov Lev, The State and Society in
Fatimid Egypt (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1991); Paula Sanders, Ritual, Politics, and the City in Fatimid Cairo (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1994).
[28] Marshall G. S. Hodgson , "Al-Darazi
and Hamza in the Origin of the Druze Religion," Journal of the American Oriental Society 82 (1962): 5-20;
Abu-Izzeddin, The Druzes; Bryer, 52.2 (1975): 47-83,
52.2 (1975): 239-62, and 53.1 (1976): 5-27. See also: Encyclopaedia Britannica article on the Druze.
|
|